Nodelman, P. 'Becoming
What You Eat.' The Horn book
magazine, 2006, 82:3, pp.265-271
Becoming What You Eat
Perry Nodelman
Ihave eaten
sardines and the occasional doughnut. I have eaten many potatoes—mostly fried.
Fortunately for me, however, there’s no truth in the saying, “You are what you
eat.” I’m not a sardine, nor a potato, nor yet a doughnut. Nevertheless, I’ve
often been invited to think of myself as being these things or wanting to
become them. “So you want to be a sardine,” says the opening of Chris Raschka’s
Arlene Sardine (Orchard). It assumes I already want to be what I’m
reading about—which, in the case of this sardine or of the potatoes in Toby Speed’s
Brave Potatoes (Putnam) or the doughnut hero of Laurie Keller’s Arnie
the Doughnut (Holt), is what I eat. This is strange. Why would I want to think
of myself as being a sardine or a potato or a doughnut? Sardines are, surely,
uncomfortably oily, and they live too close to their neighbors. Potatoes have
too many eyes and not enough mouths or ears—or brains. Doughnuts have an empty
hole at the very core of their being. Above all, doughnuts—and potatoes, and
even sardines—get eaten. Yet many children’s books describe the lives of more
or less edible beings in ways that clearly invite young readers to identify with
them.
Nor
is it just food. Children’s stories so often ask children to see themselves as
talking ducks or bunnies or even potatoes that we simply take it for granted.
Such stories exist, probably, because we tend to believe that children imagine
the world as filled with beings like themselves—that it’s childlike thinking to
give sardines consciousness, to believe that the doughnut you’re eating wishes
to give you the pleasure of eating it, or the sidewalk you tripped on was
deliberately out to get you. In my own experience, children aren’t always so
egocentric—and in any case, it was Chris Raschka, an adult, who thought up the
hopeful sardine, and Toby
Speed, an adult, who cooked up
the brave potatoes. By presenting children with this world of sentient objects
as a given, as what we believe they already imagine and ought therefore to
enjoy, we
265
266
adults may well be teaching
children how to be childlike—encouraging them to think in the ways we expect
and, presumably, approve of for children.
Our
ideas about identifying with literary characters—seeing ourselves as the
sardines we read about—confirm that. As usually described, the process has two
stages. First, you recognize that a character shares characteristics with
you—that because you are small and bored, you can recognize yourself in the
small bored rabbit in a story. Then, you follow along as something happens to the
character that leads it to a realization and thus teaches it a lesson—a lesson
that, since you identify, you take to be a truth about yourself. If the
potatoes turn out to be brave, then so can you be. This process assumes that
identification leads to a change in attitude— to learning.
At
first glance, identification seems to be egocentric. Adults I talk with about
literature often tell me that they don’t like certain texts because they can’t,
as they say, “relate” to them. Sometimes they mean merely that they find the
texts boring or confusing. Often, though, they mean they can’t understand the
aspects of a text that diverge from experiences they’re already familiar with,
or that they are unwilling to empathize with its characters, or that they can’t
see the characters’ situations as relevant to their own lives and concerns. All
these suggest the same strategy for responding to stories: reading them as if
they were about ourselves. But literature can be about people unlike ourselves
and still be entertaining, can give us rich insights into the lives of others
as well as confirmation of ourselves. Furthermore, taking pleasure in depictions
of The Other is something young children can learn— and the sooner, surely, the
better.
In
any case, identifying with a character is rarely if ever an act of
self-confirmation. It almost always contains an invitation to change as the
characters we identify with change—to become different from what we already
are. Furthermore, the original step of making an identification with a character
also involves learning and change. It’s an act of self-perception, a way of
understanding what you are already: “I am small like the sardine. I am
therefore sardinelike.” That’s why identification, doubly determined to
convince us of someone else’s idea of who we should be, is dangerous. Consider,
for instance, Raschka’s phrase “So you want to be a sardine.” It invites
agreement: “Of course! You’re right! I do want to become a sardine!” In
assuming readers are already hoping what it seems
266
267
to want them to
hope for, this sentence appears to invite a thoughtless agreement with it and
an acceptance of the surely questionable desirability of sardinehood. It hooks
us before the rest of the book spells out the awful implications of being hooked.
Unless,
of course, readers are able to resist the identification. Many adults would
agree with the views expressed by an Amazon reviewer of Arlene Sardine:
“What’s not okay here? Manipulation by the author to try and convince the
reader that it was okay for Arlene to want to become a sardine.” While adults
with views like these clearly haven’t accepted the invitation to identify
themselves, they worry that less experienced readers will accept it and be
endangered by it. They believe that identification ought to happen— for how
else are we to socialize children into an acceptance of our view of who they
ought to be?—and usually does. And that’s why youngsters need to be protected
from the likes of Arlene Sardine.
If readers like
the Amazon reviewer trusted their own refusal of Raschka’s invitation to
sardinehood, they might consider another possibility—that there’s something
fishy about this book, something that subverts identification. So you want to
be a sardine? Frankly, no, I don’t. The strange assumption that I do makes me
keenly aware that I don’t. Surely few people ever have. Surely, specifically,
few children have. This might be less a book
267
268
to identify with
than a book about the perils of identifying. There are clearly perils. While few
of us might wish sardinehood on our young, there’s a long history of stories that
make no bones about inviting children to identify with equally repressed and
therefore repressive objects: little engines that learn to stay on the tracks
or little fish that learn to stop wanting to be more than they already are.
Furthermore, even if the engine discovered that tracks are an evil capitalist
plot or the fish finally embraced change and became a bluebird, a young
reader’s acceptance of the identification itself represents a form of
repression, an identity molded to suit the needs and desires of others. I find
myself wondering if inviting children to identify is always dangerous, even
when its educational goals are ones we might approve of. If so, might there be
ways we can arm young readers against the harm? Are there stories that ask for
identification but also include elements that undermine it—as Arlene Sardine
appears to do? Or can we discover reading practices that might create a
safe distance even in stories that don’t appear to want to allow it? In search
of some answers, I’ll look at a few stories that invite identification
specifically with268
269
food. The most
significant fact about food is that we do eat it. Cookies and parts of pigs and
lambs get chewed, swallowed, devoured, destroyed. Any story inviting
identification with food is inherently a horror story. Like all horror stories,
like Dracula’s evocation of the fear of the alien invader, it is a
confrontation with things we find frightening that allows us to confront and
control our fears.
Many children’s
stories are about eaters being eaten or being threatened with being eaten.
Little Red Riding Hood brings food to her grandmother, but nearly gets eaten
herself before she ends up enjoying lunch with a woodsman. The Gingerbread Man,
baked in order to fill the role of a child for a childless old man and woman,
runs away from childhood only to find the fate of all other gingerbread men, in
the salivating mouth of a fox. In tales like these, young beings who reject
parental or otherwise conventional adult ideas about who they should be or how
they ought to behave risk becoming food for predators—their humanity or
childlikeness rejected or denied in favor of bodily desires that then allow
others to hunger for their bodies. Better, it seems, to be the obedient or provident
child your parents see you as and/or want to mold you into than the defenseless
and edible object you actually are. If these are horror stories, the horror is
the acknowledgment of the innate vulnerability of human bodies. We are what can
be eaten.
On
the other hand, Beatrix Potter’s Peter Rabbit steals food from Mr. McGregor’s
garden, where his father was killed and put into a pie by Mrs. McGregor—and
gets away with it, an act of resistance to being food that strangely defies his
rabbit nature. In Frank and Devin Asch’s more recent book Mr. Maxwell’s
Mouse (Kids Can), Mr. Maxwell, a fat-cat businessman—or more exactly, a fat
businessman cat—celebrates his promotion by ordering a mixed green salad and
raw mouse at the Paw and Claw restaurant. The mouse in question, unusually
talkative for an entrée, seems quite happy with his status as food until he
tricks the cat into slicing into his own tail and makes his escape. These brave
child surrogates all develop mastery not by being protected from their own
edibility by adopting others’ views of who they ought to be but by denying it
and transcending it by themselves. But like Little Red Riding Hood or the
Gingerbread Man, they can survive only if they have or develop an understanding
of themselves as being dangerously edible, in need of protection by themselves
or others. All these books express concern about the fragility of childlike
bodies—their propensity for
269
270
being weak
enough and, in their weakness, yummy enough to whet the appetites of hungry
predators. You are indeed what others eat. You need protection from would-be
eaters. In revealing how children can and do escape being eaten, these texts
are reassuring— horror stories with happy endings. But they can reassure only
those who accept the idea of their vulnerable edibility in the first place. Are
children really so frightened of their own vulnerability? Why do so many adults
want them to believe they are? Is it because we worry about their immature lack
of consciousness of their need for our protection? Or is it, sometimes, because
we worry that a mature perception of their own ability to fend for themselves
might deprive us of our significance to them? It’s interesting that Peter
Rabbit has to pay for his independent triumph with a stomachache and maternal
pampering. We adults desperately wish children to believe in their
vulnerability— to think of themselves as inherently foodlike. These texts are
wish-fulfillment fantasies for adults.
In
Arnie the Doughnut, Arnie refuses to be food, and ends up happily ever
after as a pet—a “doughnut-dog.” It’s revealing that Arnie becomes a pet—a
being both less than human and always humanized by those it lives with, a
creature existing somewhere halfway between the animal and the human, the
edible and the eater. For a lot of adults, that exactly describes childhood
itself— the state of being more than the mere animal you were born as but not
quite yet the civilized adult human you will become, a form of existence that
both allows your divergence from adult standards of rationality and behavior
and defines your need for adult supervision and control. For a lot of adults,
children and pets have all too much in common.
Personally,
I believe children deserve better. For all the charm and humor of Arnie the
Doughnut, children are not doughnuts, and inviting them to think that they
are as a way to keep them safe from their own supposed weakness is an
expression of the adult power they need defenses against. They need to be
suspicious of the process of identification. They need more Arlene Sardines.
They need more books like Eric Rohmann’s Pumpkinhead (Knopf), in which
Otho, born with a pumpkin for a head, achieves only a temporarily happy ending
that does not stop him from being edible or turn him into something more
normally human. His mother tells him, “‘You must be more careful, Otho . . .
You know the world will always be difficult for a boy with a pumpkin for a
head.’ And Otho found that suited him just fine.” Unlike Arnie, he doesn’t
270
271
have to become
something he isn’t in order to be happy—he just has to be happy about being
what he already is, an edible being who eats other edible beings, a body and
the personality more or less firmly attached to it, a paradoxical combination
of an organic substance and a human ideal of childlikeness. For all the books
in which doughnuts cease to be doughnuts and turn into something more safely
like what parents wish their children to be, child readers need more tools to
see beyond the habits of mind and the processes of reading literature that such
books take for granted. They need, in other words, to learn to read critically.
The more we help them to develop the tools to do that, the more healthy and
nutritious will be the books they read.
Perry Nodelman
teaches children’s literature at the University of Winnipeg and is the editor
of CCL,
the Canadian children’s literature journal. This article is adapted from his
Gryphon Lecture, delivered on March 3, 2005. The Gryphon
Lecture is
sponsored by the Youth Literature Interest Group at the Center for Children’s
Books at the University of Illinois at Urbana–Champaign.
No comments:
Post a Comment